Fisher Information - Definition

Definition

The Fisher information is a way of measuring the amount of information that an observable random variable X carries about an unknown parameter θ upon which the probability of X depends. The probability function for X, which is also the likelihood function for θ, is a function f(X; θ); it is the probability mass (or probability density) of the random variable X conditional on the value of θ. The partial derivative with respect to θ of the natural logarithm of the likelihood function is called the score. Under certain regularity conditions, it can be shown that the first moment of the score (that is, its expected value) is 0. The second moment is called the Fisher information:


\mathcal{I}(\theta)=\operatorname{E} \left = \int \left(\frac{\partial}{\partial\theta} \log f(X;\theta)\right)^2 f(X; \theta)\; dX,

where, for any given value of θ, the expression E denotes the conditional expectation over values for X with respect to the probability function f(x; θ) given θ. Note that . A random variable carrying high Fisher information implies that the absolute value of the score is often high. The Fisher information is not a function of a particular observation, as the random variable X has been averaged out.

Since the expectation of the score is zero, the Fisher information is also the variance of the score.

If log f(x; θ) is twice differentiable with respect to θ, and under certain regularity conditions, then the Fisher information may also be written as


\mathcal{I}(\theta) = - \operatorname{E} \left\,.

Thus, the Fisher information is the negative of the expectation of the second derivative with respect to θ of the natural logarithm of f. Information may be seen to be a measure of the "curvature" of the support curve near the maximum likelihood estimate of θ. A "blunt" support curve (one with a shallow maximum) would have a low negative expected second derivative, and thus low information; while a sharp one would have a high negative expected second derivative and thus high information.

Information is additive, in that the information yielded by two independent experiments is the sum of the information from each experiment separately:

This result follows from the elementary fact that if random variables are independent, the variance of their sum is the sum of their variances. Hence the information in a random sample of size n is n times that in a sample of size 1 (if observations are independent).

The information provided by a sufficient statistic is the same as that of the sample X. This may be seen by using Neyman's factorization criterion for a sufficient statistic. If T(X) is sufficient for θ, then

for some functions g and h. See sufficient statistic for a more detailed explanation. The equality of information then follows from the following fact:

 \frac{\partial}{\partial\theta} \log \left
= \frac{\partial}{\partial\theta} \log \left

which follows from the definition of Fisher information, and the independence of h(X) from θ. More generally, if T = t(X) is a statistic, then


\mathcal{I}_T(\theta)
\leq
\mathcal{I}_X(\theta)

with equality if and only if T is a sufficient statistic.

Read more about this topic:  Fisher Information

Famous quotes containing the word definition:

    Scientific method is the way to truth, but it affords, even in
    principle, no unique definition of truth. Any so-called pragmatic
    definition of truth is doomed to failure equally.
    Willard Van Orman Quine (b. 1908)

    I’m beginning to think that the proper definition of “Man” is “an animal that writes letters.”
    Lewis Carroll [Charles Lutwidge Dodgson] (1832–1898)

    Beauty, like all other qualities presented to human experience, is relative; and the definition of it becomes unmeaning and useless in proportion to its abstractness. To define beauty not in the most abstract, but in the most concrete terms possible, not to find a universal formula for it, but the formula which expresses most adequately this or that special manifestation of it, is the aim of the true student of aesthetics.
    Walter Pater (1839–1894)