Thomas Talbott - Problem of Evil

Problem of Evil

In the September 1987 edition of the periodical Christian Scholar's Review, Talbott sought, as he explains in a more recent comment, "to make some ideas then current in the philosophical literature available to a wider audience of non-philosophers." He sought to explain, for example, how Alvin Plantinga's Free Will Defense had transformed the way in which contemporary philosophers approach the so-called problem of evil and why, in particular, even atheistic philosophers came to abandon the claim that evil is logically inconsistent with the existence of God. But at the end of this article, Talbott also ventured into more controversial territory, suggesting ways in which even the tragic suffering of innocent children might contribute, in the end, to the future blessedness of all people (including the children who suffer). In accordance with his affirmation of universal reconciliation, he thus expressed the hopeful belief that "every innocent child who suffers will one day look upon that suffering as a privilege because of the joy it has made possible: the joy of knowing that one has been used by God in the redemption of others, the joy of that final union or reunion in which love's triumph is complete and all separation from others is finally overcome. I would ask but two things of those who reject such a view: first, that they resist the temptation to moralize, and second, that they consider the alternatives carefully."

Others have, not surprisingly, roundly criticized and even ridiculed such a view. According to John Beversluis, Emeritus Professor of Philosophy at Butler University, for example, Talbott's view is "so outrageous...that I will not dignify it with a reply....If Talbott is right, he is logically committed and morally obliged to oppose everyone dedicated to alleviating world hunger, ridding the world of terrorism, finding a cure for cancer...and so forth." But in an equally hard-hitting reply, Talbott dismisses this claim by comparing it to a more precise claim of the following form: "If Talbott is right in accepting p (where p is specifically identified), then Talbott is logically committed to q." He then points out that a cogent argument in the present context would require two things of Beversluis: "first, that he identify a relevant instance of p, and second, that he make some attempt to deduce q from p. But Beversluis," Talbott insists, "does not so much as identify the proposition that he claims logically commits me to the moral obligation he alleges; much less does he make the required deduction."

Talbott acknowledges, however, that his optimistic view could be regarded as a case of wishful thinking. But he goes on to contrast hope with despair, arguing that, unlike despair, hope is compatible with a healthy skepticism. For whereas despair typically rests upon a set of dogmatic beliefs about the future, hope does not.


"I form the light, and creae darkness: I make peace, and create evil: I the Lord do all these things." Isaiah 45-7...Evil is only a problem for those God sends it on...I read where He to Nationl Israel in the OT many times if they would repent, that He would repent of the evil He thought to do to them...God via Hitler put so much evil in Euopean Jews that it (He) drove them back to a land called Israel...God is God and Jesus is His "Only Begotten Son" entitled to all of His Fathers Titles and not His own Father...amen

Read more about this topic:  Thomas Talbott

Famous quotes containing the words problem and/or evil:

    Consciousness is what makes the mind-body problem really intractable.
    Thomas Nagel (b. 1938)

    If one does not do evil things in the daytime, one need not fear knocks on the door in the middle of the night.
    Chinese proverb.