Category Utility - Probability-theoretic Definition of Category Utility

Probability-theoretic Definition of Category Utility

The probability-theoretic definition of category utility given in Fisher (1987) and Witten & Frank (2005) is as follows:


CU(C,F) = \tfrac{1}{p} \sum_{c_j \in C} p(c_j) \left

where is a size- set of -ary features, and is a set of categories. The term designates the marginal probability that feature takes on value, and the term designates the category-conditional probability that feature takes on value given that the object in question belongs to category .

The motivation and development of this expression for category utility, and the role of the multiplicand as a crude overfitting control, is given in the above sources. Loosely (Fisher 1987), the term is the expected number of attribute values that can be correctly guessed by an observer using a probability-matching strategy together with knowledge of the category labels, while is the expected number of attribute values that can be correctly guessed by an observer the same strategy but without any knowledge of the category labels. Their difference therefore reflects the relative advantage accruing to the observer by having knowledge of the category structure.

Read more about this topic:  Category Utility

Famous quotes containing the words definition, category and/or utility:

    According to our social pyramid, all men who feel displaced racially, culturally, and/or because of economic hardships will turn on those whom they feel they can order and humiliate, usually women, children, and animals—just as they have been ordered and humiliated by those privileged few who are in power. However, this definition does not explain why there are privileged men who behave this way toward women.
    Ana Castillo (b. 1953)

    I see no reason for calling my work poetry except that there is no other category in which to put it.
    Marianne Moore (1887–1972)

    Moral sensibilities are nowadays at such cross-purposes that to one man a morality is proved by its utility, while to another its utility refutes it.
    Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900)