Bounded Quantifier - Bounded Quantifiers in Arithmetic

Bounded Quantifiers in Arithmetic

Suppose that L is the language of Peano arithmetic (the language of second-order arithmetic or arithmetic in all finite types would work as well). There are two types of bounded quantifiers: and . These quantifiers bind the number variable n and contain a numeric term t which may not mention n but which may have other free variables. (By "numeric terms" here we mean terms such as "1 + 1", "2", "2 × 3", "m + 3", etc.)

These quantifiers are defined by the following rules ( denotes formulas):

There are several motivations for these quantifiers.

  • In applications of the language to recursion theory, such as the arithmetical hierarchy, bounded quantifiers add no complexity. If is a decidable predicate then and are decidable as well.
  • In applications to the study of Peano Arithmetic, formulas are sometimes provable with bounded quantifiers but unprovable with unbounded quantifiers.

For example, there is a definition of primality using only bounded quantifiers. A number n is prime if and only if there are not two numbers strictly less than n whose product is n. There is no quantifier-free definition of primality in the language, however. The fact that there is a bounded quantifier formula defining primality shows that the primality of each number can be computably decided.

In general, a relation on natural numbers is definable by a bounded formula if and only if it is computable in the linear-time hierarchy, which is defined similarly to the polynomial hierarchy, but with linear time bounds instead of polynomial. Consequently, all predicates definable by a bounded formula are Kalmár elementary, context-sensitive, and primitive recursive.

In the arithmetical hierarchy, an arithmetical formula which contains only bounded quantifiers is called, and . The superscript 0 is sometimes omitted.

Read more about this topic:  Bounded Quantifier

Famous quotes containing the words bounded and/or arithmetic:

    I could be bounded in a nutshell and count myself a king of
    infinite space, were it not that I have bad dreams.
    William Shakespeare (1564–1616)

    Your discovery of the contradiction caused me the greatest surprise and, I would almost say, consternation, since it has shaken the basis on which I intended to build my arithmetic.... It is all the more serious since, with the loss of my rule V, not only the foundations of my arithmetic, but also the sole possible foundations of arithmetic seem to vanish.
    Gottlob Frege (1848–1925)