Typing Rules
To define the set of well typed lambda terms of a given type, we will define a typing relation between terms and types. First, we introduce typing contexts or typing environments, which are sets of typing assumptions. A typing assumption has the form, meaning has type .
The typing relation indicates that is a term of type in context . It is therefore said that " is well-typed (at )". Instances of the typing relation are called typing judgements. The validity of a typing judgement is shown by providing a typing derivation, constructed using typing rules (wherein the premises above the line allow us to derive the conclusion below the line). Simply-typed lambda calculus uses these rules:
(1) (2) |
(3) (4) |
In other words,
- If has type in the context, we know that has type .
- Term constants have the appropriate base types.
- If, in a certain context with having type, has type, then, in the same context without, has type .
- If, in a certain context, has type, and has type, then has type .
Examples of closed terms, i.e. terms typable in the empty context, are:
- For every type, a term (the I-combinator/identity function),
- For types, a term (the K-combinator), and
- For types, a term (the S-combinator).
These are the typed lambda calculus representations of the basic combinators of combinatory logic.
Each type is assigned an order, a number . For base types, ; for function types, . That is, the order of a type measures the depth of the most left-nested arrow. Hence:
Read more about this topic: Simply Typed Lambda Calculus
Famous quotes containing the word rules:
“For rhetoric, he could not ope
His mouth, but out there flew a trope;
And when he happend to break off
I th middle of his speech, or cough,
H had hard words ready to show why,
And tell what rules he did it by;”
—Samuel Butler (16121680)