De Monarchia - Argument

Argument

It is made up of three books, but the most significant is the third, in which Dante most explicitly confronts the subject of relations between the Pope and the Emperor. Dante firstly condemns the theocratic conception of the power elaborated by the Roman Church and solemnly confirmed by the papal bull Unam sanctam of 1302. The theocratic conception assigned all power to the Pope, making his authority superior to that of the Emperor: this meant that the Pope could also legitimately intervene in the matters usually in the sphere of secular authority.

Against this theocratic conception, Dante expressed his need for another strong Holy Roman Emperor and proposed the idea that man essentially pursues two ends: the happiness of earthly life and that of eternal life. Dante argues that to the Pope is assigned the management of men's eternal life (though he still recognizes this as the higher of the two), but to the Emperor is assigned the task of leading men towards earthly happiness. From this he derives the autonomy of the temporal sphere, under the Emperor, from the spiritual sphere, under the Pope - the pontiff's authority should not influence that of the Emperor in their competing tasks.

Dante wanted to demonstrate that the Holy Roman Emperor and the Pope were both human and that both derived their power and authority directly from God. To understand this it is necessary to think that man is the only thing to occupy an intermediate position between corruptibility and incorruptibility. If it is considered that man is only made up of two parts, that is to say the soul and the body, he is corruptible - only in terms of the soul is he incorruptible. Man, then, has the function of uniting corruptibility with incorruptibility. The Pope and Emperor were both human, and no peer had power over another peer. Only a higher power could judge the two "equal swords," as each was given power by God to rule over their respected domains.

Read more about this topic:  De Monarchia

Famous quotes containing the word argument:

    The argument is over.
    St. Augustine (354–430)

    Argument is conclusive ... but ... it does not remove doubt, so that the mind may rest in the sure knowledge of the truth, unless it finds it by the method of experiment.... For if any man who never saw fire proved by satisfactory arguments that fire burns ... his hearer’s mind would never be satisfied, nor would he avoid the fire until he put his hand in it ... that he might learn by experiment what argument taught.
    Roger Bacon (c. 1214–1294)

    Any authentic work of art must start an argument between the artist and his audience.
    Rebecca West (1892–1983)